Seminar in Philosophy, Logic and Games | |||||
A link for each seminar is to be posted here shortly before it begins. |
Sunday, September 11, 10:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Sao Paulo |
|||||
A Polynomial Decision for 3 − SAT Abstract. We present a solution, satisfiable or unsatisfiable, bounded in Space and Time for 3 − SAT formulas. First, we rewrite a given 3 − SAT formula as a combination of 2 − SAT formulas, keeping in mind the logical equivalence on this process. Using the fact that solving 2 − SAT formulas is a well known method, we group unsatisfiable combinations in the array. The final process, after obtaining all unsatisfiable combinations involves the procedure to verify we wrote all possible groups, an unsatisfiable formula or no, a satisfiable formula. We briefly describe our approach as published in the repository arXiv, http://arxiv.org/abs/2208.12598 We welcome all! |
Wednesday, August 31, 9:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
IIT-Kanpur |
|||||
Generalizations of Topological System: The Unifying Framework of Logic, Topology and Algebra Abstract. In this talk I would like to focus on the idea of topological system, introduced by S. Vickers in 1989, and explain how topological system can unify the concepts of topology, algebra (in particular frame) and (geometric) logic in one framework. I will discuss the generalizations of topological system done by us and other researchers so far. If time permits I will delve into one of the generalizations in detail. |
Wednesday, August 17, 9:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Indiana University |
|||||
Normative Theory for Two Person Sequential Decision Games Abstract. I present a 'normative' theory for two selfish rational agents making alternating decisions until a joint payoff is reached. I assume the agents reason alike and that both know the entire decision tree and all the joint payoffs. Because neither agent know the subjective utility of payoffs for the other, I assume the goal for both is maximizing the rank of the payoff achievable (more is preferred to less). For the same reason, and because the agents are rational, threats to take a loss in order to inflict a greater loss on the other agent are not allowed. Also for the same reason decision strategies based on probability mixtures of payoffs are not possible, except uniform random choice among good payoffs for both when neither can enforce a preferred choice among those. Under these assumptions the theory provides a unique solution for any finite decision tree. The reasoning for the algorithm producing the solution will likely be accepted by most theorists when the two agents bargain to reach a binding contract. I argue the same solution applies without a binding contract, and even when the two agents do not communicate (but many experts might not agree). Although the agents are selfish, the algorithm generally gives cooperative decision solutions (in many cases where Nash equilibria do not), a result due to the agents each taking into account that other agent has the same selfish goal and uses the same reasoning processes. |
Wednesday, August 10, 9:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Northwestern University |
|||||
Critical-Mass Equilibrium in n-Person Games‖Slides Abstract. Since the 1950s, analysis of strategic interaction is based on the play of hypothetical equilibria of strategic games chosen by analysts. The quality of the analysts’ recommendations depends critically on the viability of their chosen hypothetical equilibria. |
Wednesday, August 3, 9:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University College London |
|||||
Reasoning about Discourse with Modal Lambek Calculus Abstract. In 1958 Lambek proposed the logic of a residuated monoid to reason about syntax of natural language. This logic was successfully applied to sentential fragments of English and many other languages, but has not gone beyond sentence boundaries and applied to discourse structures. An example of discourse is "John slept. He snored." where the discourse structure is the anaphoric coreference relation between `John' and `He'.. In this talk, I will show how endowing Lambek Calculus with special modalities overcomes this shortcoming. I will go over a tensor algebraic semantics for the logic where the modal formulae are Fock spaces. This semantics enables us to relate the logic with recent advances in quantum circuits. We have been running experiments on the IBMq quantum computing devices and I will show some of our results. The talk is joint work with Hadi Wazni, Ian Lo Kin and Lachlan McPheat. |
Wednesday, July 27, 9:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Luxembourg |
|||||
Logics for the Conceptual (Re-)Construction of (Epistemic) Rights Abstract. The theory of normative positions is a formal theory for reasoning about different types of (legal) rights and duties. In this talk, I will introduce my multi-modal logic-based approach to this theory and show how we have used and extended that for the conceptual analysis of some epistemic rights like the right to know and the freedom of thought. |
Sunday, July 3, 10:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Finite and Infinite Dialogues Abstract. But how does he know where and how he is to look up the word 'red' and what he is to do with the word 'five'? Well, I assume he acts as I have described. Explanations come to an end somewhere. — Ludwig WittgensteinWe show how conversations between two people change their knowledge, even by statements of the form "I don't know." There are cases where finite dialogues suffice but also cases where the dialogue needs to be infinite and then the Cantor-Bendixson theorem about isolated points in a topological space becomes relevant. |
Sunday, June 5, 12:00 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Johns Hopkins University |
|||||
Are Myersonian Common-Knowledge Events Common Knowledge? Abstract. This note presents a microfoundation for the belief-based common knowledge concept proposed by Holmstrom and Myerson (1983) and further refined by Myerson (1997), by showing its equivalence to the hierarchical description of common knowledge, agent i knows that j knows that . . . knows event E. Furthermore, it provides a useful algorithm to find common knowledge events. |
Sunday, May 22, 12:00 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
CUNY Graduate Center |
|||||
Beyond Knowledge of the Model‖Slides Abstract. The principal motivation of this work is to display the sense in which the epistemic reading of a Kripke model tacitly requires common knowledge of the model, CKM. This requirement significantly restricts the amount of epistemic situations we are able to consider. We explore possible worlds epistemic models in a general setting without CKM assumptions and show that such models can be identified with observable submodels of Kripke models. We argue that such observable models offer a new level of generality and conceptual clarity in epistemic modeling. Similar analysis applies to intuitionistic models. |
Sunday, March 20, 12:00 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Helsinki |
|||||
Game Theory, Cheap Talk, and Post-Truth Politics Abstract. I offer two potential diagnoses of the behavioral norms governing post!truth politics by comparing the view of language, communication, and truth!telling put forward by David Lewis (extended by game theorists), and John Searle. My first goal is to specify the different ways in which Lewis, and game theorists more generally, in contrast to Searle (in the company of Paul Grice and Jürgen Habermas), go about explaining the normativity of truthfulness within a linguistic community. The main difference is that for Lewis and game theorists, “truthful” signaling follows from an alignment of interests, and deception follows from mixed motives leading to the calculation that sending false information is better for oneself. Following in the Enlightenment tradition, Searle argues that practical reasoning, which involves mastery of at least one language, requires that actors intend to communicate. This intention includes constraining the content of statements to uphold veracity conditions. After distinguishing between these two accounts, I will articulate the implications for explaining, and even informing actions, constitutive of post!truth politics. I argue that the strategic view of communication is sufficient neither to model everyday conversation nor to reflect a public sphere useful for democratic government. Both the pedagogy of strategic communication as cheap talk, and its concordance with new digital information technologies, challenge norms of truthful-ness that underlie modern institutions essential to an effective public sphere. |
Sunday, January 9, 10:00 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Hong Kong University of Science and Technology |
|||||
Animal Consciousness and Phenomenal Concepts Abstract. A phenomenal concept is a concept that one possesses only if one has the relevant experience. In this talk, I explore which non-human animal species are phenomenally conscious. I argue that the phenomenal concept theorists, namely, those who believe that we acquire phenomenal concepts through being acquainted with the relevant experience, can never succeed in providing a method to determine which species of non-human animals are phenomenally conscious. I do so by discussing several ways for a phenomenal concept theorist to explain which animal species are conscious, such as neuro-identity theory, functionalism, and behaviourism, and list the problems with them. I then illustrate the trouble with various possible alternatives for answering the question of animal consciousness, such as analogical inference, similarity inference, inference by prototype theory, and scientific inference to the best explanation. |
Friday, December 10, 10:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Ljubljana |
|||||
What is Information and How to Measure it?‖Slides Abstract. In view of the duality between subsets and quotient sets (= partitions = equivalence relations), the Boolean logic of subsets (usually presented as "propositional" logic) has a dual logic of partitions. The quantitative version of Boolean logic is the Boole-Laplace notion of logical probability. Gian-Carlo Rota held that probability is to subsets as information is to partitions, so the quantitative version of partition logic is the theory of logical entropy. This talk is an introduction to logical entropy as the natural measure (in the sense of measure theory) of information as distinctions. It is also shown that the Shannon entropy (which is not a measure) is a uniform transform of logical entropy that is a different quantification of the same notion of information as distinctions. |
Friday, November 5, 10:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Amsterdam |
|||||
Computing Social Behavior‖Slides Abstract. Recently, epistemic-social phenomena have received more attention from the logic community, analyzing peer pressure, studying informational cascades, inspecting priority-based peer influence, modeling diffusion and prediction, and examining reflective social influence. In this presentation, I will contribute to this line of work and focus in particular on the logical features of social group creation. I pay attention to the mechanisms which indicate when agents can form a team based on the correspondence in their set of features (behavior, opinions, etc.). Our basic approach uses a semi-metric on the set of agents, which is used to construct a network topology. This structure is then extended with epistemic features to represent the agents' epistemic states, allowing us to explore group-creation alternatives where what matters is not only the agent's differences but also what they know about them. The logical settings in this work make use of the techniques of dynamic epistemic logic to represent group-creation actions, to define new languages in order to describe their effects, and to provide sound and complete axiom systems. This talk is based on joint work with Fernando Velazquez Quesada. |
Thursday, October 7, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Michigan |
|||||
Negative probabilities: What are they for? Abstract. The topic may sound nonsensical. The standard frequential interpretation of probabilities makes no sense for negative probabilities. Yet negative probabilities are profitably used in quantum physics and elsewhere. So what are they? What is their intrinsic meaning? We don't know. There are attempts in the literature to provide meaning for negative probabilities but, in our judgement, the problem is wide open. |
Thursday, September 23, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Northeastern University |
|||||
Probabilities of Conditionals & Conditional Probabilities — Revisited Abstract. Lewis's (1976) triviality argument against The Equation (a.k.a, Adams's Thesis) rests on an implausibly strong presupposition about the nature of (epistemic) rational requirements. Interestingly, Lewis (1980) later rejected this presupposition. In his discussion of the Principal Principle, Lewis assumes something weaker, and more reasonable, about the nature of rational requirements. In this paper, I explain how to apply the insights of Lewis (1980) to repair Lewis's earlier (1976) discussion. This leads to a more reasonable rendition of The Equation — one which is (a) immune from triviality, and (b) a better candidate for a (bona fide) rational requirement. |
Thursday, September 2, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Cooperation, Psychological Game Theory, and Limitations of Rationality in Social Interaction Discussion. Andrew M. Coleman's "Cooperation, Psychological Game Theory, and Limitations of Rationality in Social Interaction," Behaviorial and Brain Sciences, 26(2): 139-153, April 2003. |
Thursday, August 26, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Cooperation, Psychological Game Theory, and Limitations of Rationality in Social Interaction Discussion. Andrew M. Coleman's "Cooperation, Psychological Game Theory, and Limitations of Rationality in Social Interaction," Behaviorial and Brain Sciences, 26(2): 139-153, April 2003. |
Thursday, August 19, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Princeton University |
|||||
Risk and Rationality Abstract. When making decisions under risk, individuals are forced to consider how their choices will turn out under various circumstances, and decide how to trade off the possibility that a choice will turn out well against the possibility that it will turn out poorly. The orthodox view is that there is only one acceptable way to do this: rational individuals must maximize expected utility. I argue, however, that the orthodox theory dictates an overly narrow way in which considerations about risk can play a role in an individual’s choices; and I propose an alternative theory of rational decision-making. This new theory allows us to isolate the distinct roles that beliefs, desires, and risk-attitudes play in decision-making. It also vindicates the ordinary decision-maker, from the point of view of even ideal rationality. |
Thursday, August 12, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science |
|||||
Regret Minimization in Extensive-form Games Abstract. It is well known that regret minimization in repeated normal-form games generates mediated equilibrium behavior. More specifically, external regret minimization converges to coarse correlated equilibrium, while internal regret minimization converges to correlated equilibrium. In this work, we explore the much richer space of possible deviations in extensive-form games (external, internal, counterfactual, causal, etc.), and establish the relationships among the mediated equilibria that arise when regret is minimized with respect to these deviation sets. Additionally, we define a generic algorithm, called extensive-form regret minimization (EFR), which minimizes the regret of a given deviation set chosen from a natural class -- the behavioral deviations -- that subsumes all of the aforementioned classes. EFR's computational requirements and regret bound scale closely with the complexity of the given deviation set, so we focus on a subset of the class of behavioral deviations, which we call partial sequence deviations, that is both efficient to work with and subsumes previously studied sets. Experimentally, EFR with partial sequence deviations outperforms existing regret minimization algorithms (e.g., counterfactual regret minimization) when playing games in the OpenSpiel environment. |
Thursday, August 5, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Counterfactuals and Causality Abstract. It is true that if Oswald did not shoot Kennedy in Dallas then someone else did. But it is doubtful that if Oswald had not shot Kennedy in Dallas someone else would have. Why are they different? |
Thursday, July 29, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
CUNY Graduate Center |
|||||
Probabilistic Causation: de facto Dependence and Modal Relativism Abstract. On some interpretations of quantum mechanics - on the orthodox interpretation and the GRW interpretation - the world is fundamentally probabilistic. Furthermore, at least some of these fundamental probabilities can propagate up to the macroscopic scale. If either of these is the right view, then some causes will not be nomologically sufficient for their effects. In order to make sense of the causal relation in these circumstances, we need a probabilistic theory of causation. In his 2021 book, Causation, Luke Fenton-Glynn argues that the most promising such theory is a de facto dependence view that relies on probabilistic causal models. After presenting the view, I will first observe that it leaves certain questions open. I will then argue that the best answer to these questions results in a view of causation whereby one particular thing causes a second only relative to a set of background possibilities. The argument is analogous to one I make in the deterministic case. I call this view "Modal Relativism." |
Thursday, July 22, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Boston University |
|||||
Russell, Gödel and Early Wittgenstein Summary. Floyd's latest scholarly triumph, Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics, is to appear this month. |
Thursday, July 15, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
NIAS-MIT |
|||||
Cognitive Epistemology Abstract. The single scientist world is over. Data is being collected in parallel by several labs and their sensor networks. Even more importantly, we are keenly aware that biological organisms are knowledge producing beings. Our archetype is no longer the scientist collecting data in slow motion, but the animal constantly harvesting knowledge from the world and responding appropriately. |
Thursday, June 17, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Brooklyn College and CUNY Graduate Center |
|||||
Diagonalization, Fixed Points, and Self-reference. Abstract. Some of the most profound and famous theorems in mathematics and computer science of the past 150 years can simultaneously be seen as a consequence of diagonalization, as a fixed-point theorem, and as an instance of a self-referential paradox. These results include Cantor's theorems about different levels of infinity; Russell's paradox; Gödel's incompleteness theorem; Turing's halting problem; and much more. Amazingly, all these diverse theorems and all viewpoints can be seen as instances of a single simple theorem of basic category theory. We describe this theorem and show some of the instances. A large part of the talk will be a discussion of diagonalization proofs, fixed point theorems, and self- referential paradoxes that fail to be an instance of this categorical theorem. We will meet another categorical idea that unifies some of these ideas. No category theory is needed for this talk. |
Friday, June 11, 10:30 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Institute of Mathematical Sciences, Chennai |
|||||
A Formal Model for the Emergence of Collective Memory‖Slides Abstract. According to Susan Sontag, "What is called collective memory is not a remembering but a stipulating." Then one can ask, what is the rationale followed by a group in ascribing / stipulating collective importance to events and their remembering? We present a formal model for collective memory based on automata. Agents keep signalling within neighbourhoods, and depending on the support each signal gets, some signals "win." By agents interacting between different neighbourhoods,'inluence' spreads and sometimes, a collective signal emerges. Interestingly enough, the natural model for such memory is the Parikh automaton that computes exactly the semi-linear predicates. In the talk we discuss the philosophical and logical aspects of the problem and raise questions, some of which can be addressed in the model. |
Thursday, June 3, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Brooklyn College |
|||||
Judgement Aggregation Discussion. Deciding courses of action as a group is common as the old saying goes "No man is an island." Since turning the votes of many into one outcome is such an integral part of our experiences one must ask if our method of decision making is without flaw. In the talk I will be examining various different rules for judgement aggregation to see if a perfect system exists. This will include going over different characteristics we would expect the rule to have as well as examining what characteristics we will have to relax to avoid certain outcomes. |
Thursday, May 27, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Johns Hopkins |
|||||
Continuity Postulates and Solvability Axioms in Decision Theory‖Slides Ali Khan is Abram Hutzler Professor of Political Economy with the Department of Economics at Johns Hopkins University. |
Thursday, May 20, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Brown University |
|||||
Davidson Causality: The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Regulatory Genome Abstract. In his book The Regulatory Genome: Gene Regulatory Networks (GRN) in Development and Evolution (Academic Press 2006), Eric Davidson, the foremost experimentalist of regulatory genomics, forcefully reminds us that in the scientific method, causality is everything; all other approaches are just distractions. In contrast, Davidson — a notoriously elegant writer — offers devastating criticism of the “posterior Biology” approaches all too impatiently employed today — the “measure first” expression of thousands of genes and then “computationally infer Biology.” The last century’s luminaries of mathematical statistics taught us in no uncertain terms that causality cannot be inferred from statistical tables. Davidson aligns with them, adding to their argument a practical dose of reality. The exquisite regulatory mechanisms, locked down by evolution, can only be revealed through systematic experimental perturbations. In the absence of the ocean deep “prior Biology” knowledge, no amount of clustering statistics, or other skinny deep dives, would be able infer “Biology.” Like his mentor Max Delbruck, and with the sea urchin genome in hand, Eric Davidson become the leading liberator of quantitative principles of cell regulation, trapped in the qualitative, descriptive world of biology without genomic sequence. |
Thursday, May 13, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
University of Maryland |
|||||
Epistemic Networks for Imprecise Agents‖Slides Abstract. What is the best form for social influence to take? Are all policies which aim to increase the amount of interaction over a particular issue likely to be successful in their aims? In this talk, I will survey some models that have been proposed by economists and social epistemologists to address these questions. These models typically assume that the agents have precise beliefs about the proposition that they are trying to learn. However, in many learning situations, at least some of the agents may have imprecise beliefs about the proposition that they are trying to learn. The second part of the talk will report on some work in progress with Paul Pedersen about how best to design communication networks when some agents have imprecise beliefs. |
Thursday, May 6, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
The Graduate Center, CUNY |
|||||
Nietzsche on Logic, Philosophy, and Moral Values‖Slides Abstract. Studies in logic rarely ever mention Fredrich Nietzsche. There is very little literature on Nietzsche’s critique of classical logic and there is no indication that he followed the developments that were occurring in the field in the 19th century by contemporaneous thinkers such as George Boole, Frege, or Augustus De Morgan. Yet, logic is central to Nietzsche’s seminal work, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, henceforth referred to as BGE. Believing that classical logic falsely reinforces the religious promise of absolutism and certainty, Nietzsche rejects the possibility of a priori truths qua truth, but embraces logic to the extent that he considers it the vehicle that systematically discharges a philosopher’s energy and morality onto the world. |
Thursday, April 29, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Brooklyn College |
|||||
Limitations of Social Choice Procedures‖Slides Discussion. We will first define a social welfare function that takes in the input of individual preference lists and outputs a single social preference list. Then we will define a "weakly reasonable" social welfare function in the sense that it describes the will of the people. This function must satisfy PAR, IIA, and monotonicity. However, the unsettling conclusion we will reach is that the only social welfare function that satisfies these conditions is a dictatorship. |
Thursday, April 22, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
John Jay |
|||||
Knowledge, Behavior, and Rationality: Rationalizability in Epistemic Games Abstract. In strategic situations, agents base actions on knowledge and beliefs. This includes knowledge about others’ strategies and preferences over strategy profiles, but also about other external factors. Bernheim and Pearce in 1984 independently defined the game theoretic solution concept of rationalizability, which is built on the premise that rational agents will only take actions that are the best response to some situation that they consider possible. This accounts for other agents’ rationality as well, limiting the strategies to which a particular agent must respond, enabling further elimination until the strategies stabilize. We seek to generalize rationalizability to account not only for actions, but knowledge of the world as well. This will enable us to examine the interplay between action based and knowledge based rationality. We give an account of what it means for an action to be rational relative to a particular state of affairs, and in turn relative to a state of knowledge. We present a class of games, Epistemic Messaging Games (EMG), wit ha communication stage that clarifies the epistemic state among the players prior to the players’ actions. We use a history based model, which frames individual knowledge in terms of local projections of a global history. With this framework, we give an account of rationalizability for subclasses of EMG |
Thursday, April 15, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Computer Science |
|||||
Actual Causality: A Survey Abstract. What does it mean that an event C "actually caused" event E? The problem of defining actual causation goes beyond mere philosophical speculation. For example, in many legal arguments, it is precisely what needs to be established in order to determine responsibility. (What exactly was the actual cause of the car accident or the medical problem?) The philosophy literature has been struggling with the problem of defining causality since the days of Hume, in the 1700s. Many of the definitions have been couched in terms of counterfactuals. (C is a cause of E if, had C not happened, then E would not have happened.) In 2001, Judea Pearl and I introduced a new definition of actual cause, using Pearl's notion of structural equations to model counterfactuals. The definition has been revised twice since then, extended to deal with notions like "responsibility" and "blame", and applied in databases and program verification. I survey the last 15 years of work here, including joint work with Judea Pearl, Hana Chockler, and Chris Hitchcock. The talk will be completely self-contained. |
Thursday, April 8, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Korea University |
|||||
Buddha versus Popper Abstract. We discuss two approaches to life: presentism and futurism. We locate presentism within various elements of Buddhism, in the form of advice to live in the present and not to allow the future to hinder us from living in the ever present now. By contrast, futurism, which we identify with Karl Popper, advises us to think of future consequences before we act, and to act now for a better future. Of course, with its emphasis on a well-defined path to an ideal future ideally culminating in enlightenment, Buddhism undoubtedly has elements of futurism as well. We do not intend to determine which of these two approaches to time is more dominant in Buddhism, nor how the two approaches are best understood within Buddhism; but simply we intend to compare and contrast these two approaches, using those presentist elements of Buddhism as representative of presentism while contrasting them with those elements of futurism to be found in Popper and others. We will discuss various aspects of presentism and futurism, such as Ruth Millikan’s Popperian animal, the psychologist Howard Rachlin’s social and temporal discounting, and even the popular but controversial idea, YOLO (you only live once). The primary purpose of this paper is to contrast one with the other. The central question of ethics is: How should one live? Our variation on that question is: When should one live? We conjecture that the notion of flow, developed by Csikszentmihalyi, may be a better optimal choice between these two positions. |
Thursday, March 25, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
The Logic of Knowledge Based Obligation Abstract. Our obligations depend on what we know. If we do not know that we need to do X then there is no obligation to actually do X. However, sometimes there is also an obligation to know and hence also an obligation to inform. We look into the temporal logic of such issues, relying on work by John Horty and by Parikh and Ramanujam. |
Thursday, March 18, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Mathematics |
|||||
Discussion. Christian Trudeau's "From the Bankruptcy Problem and its Concede-and-Divide Solution to the Assignment Problem and its Fair Division Solution." |
Thursday, March 11, 7:15 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Farmingdale State College |
|||||
Polarized Population Under Imitation Dynamics in Complex Networks Abstract. Evolutionary game theory is applied in a variety of settings, ranging from economics to socio-technical networks. The core concept in evolutionary game theory is evolutionary dynamics, which determines the composition of strategies in the population at steady state. Most evolutionary dynamics are modelled to descriptively showcase the utility derived from interactions between random pairs of players in well-mixed populations, or random pairs of neighbours in structured populations. In real-life social and socio-technical networks, it is more appropriate to evaluate a player's utility as a collection of interactions with its neighbours. To understand this; in practice, people form opinions by means of observation and imitation, by not just one friend, but a collection of friends. This paper displays a variation of the pairwise imitation dynamics where players imitate the most well-off neighbour. This process is memory-less i.e., players only use the outcome of the current game to determine their strategies in subsequent games. Empirical results demonstrate that in real-life social networks, this imitation dynamic leads to a polarized population with games that have multiple pure strategy Nash equilibria such as the Stag-Hunt game and anti-coordination games like Hawk-Dove, where an "undecided" population indefinitely swings between two strategies. |
Thursday, March 4, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Graduate Center, CUNY |
|||||
Causal Models as Relative to Modal Profile Abstract. A recent development in the philosophy of causation uses the framework of causal models, such as structural equation models, to define actual causation. There are two components to such a definition. The first is to identify how to define causation in terms of a given model or given class of models. The second is to provide an account of what qualifies models as given – or apt – such that they can be plugged into the first stage. A naïve hypothesis is that a model is apt just in case it is accurate. In this talk I will argue, however, that the accuracy of a model is not a determinate function of a model, an interpretation, and a situation. A given model on a given interpretation can still be deemed accurate or inaccurate of the same situation. As I demonstrate, this is because accuracy is relative to a set of background possibilities – what I call a modal profile. I argue that this reveals a heretofore hidden element in how causal models represent – that models represent situations only relative to some modal profile or other. I propose that this calls for an additional component of an interpretation: an interpretation is an assignment of content to the variables and a specification of modal profile. |
Thursday, February 25, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Covid-19 and Knowledge based Computation Abstract. The purpose of this project is to combine insights from the logic of knowledge (act according to what you know), and graph theory (spread of infection follows the edges of a graph). We show how knowledge based algorithms can be used to combine safety with economic and social activity. |
Thursday, February 18, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Computer Science |
|||||
Discussion.Chapter 6, "Two-Person Cooperative Games" (spec. pp. 114-124), from R. Duncan Luce and Howard Raiffa's Games and Decisions. |
Thursday, February 11, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Mathematics |
|||||
Discussion. Robert J. Aumann and Michael Maschler's "Game Theoretic Analysis of a Bankruptcy Problem from the Talmud," Journal of Economic Theory, 36(2): 195-213, August 1985. |
Thursday, February 4, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Discussion. Jan van Eijck and Rineke Verbrugge's"Formal Approaches to Social Procedures," from Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |
Thursday, January 28, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Thursday, January 21, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Discussion.Chapter 4, "Conflict," from A.D. Taylor and A.M. Pacelli's Mathematics and Politics: Strategy, Voting, Power and Proof |
Thursday, January 14, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Brookyln College |
|||||
Discussion.Chapter 3, "Political Power," from A.D. Taylor and A.M. Pacelli's Mathematics and Politics: Strategy, Voting, Power and Proof |
Thursday, January 7, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Discussion.Chapter 2, "Yes-No Voting," from A.D. Taylor and A.M. Pacelli's Mathematics and Politics: Strategy, Voting, Power and Proof |
Wednesday, December 30, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Discussion.Chapter 1, "Social Choice," from A.D. Taylor and A.M. Pacelli's Mathematics and Politics: Strategy, Voting, Power and Proof |
Thursday, December 17, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Linguistics |
|||||
Language and Logic: Ideas and Controversies in the History of Formal Semantics ‖Slides Abstract. The history of formal semantics and pragmatics over the last 50 years is a story of collaboration among linguists, logicians, and
philosophers. Since this talk is for a seminar in philosophy, logic, and games, and I’m a linguist, I’ll emphasize aspects of the pre-history and history of formal semantics that concern the relation between language and logic, not presupposing knowledge of linguistics. Logicians have often been concerned with language in a “negative” way: the development of formal logical languages has often been motivated by perceived inadequacies in natural language for purposes of argumentation. Russell and Strawson, who had many disagreements about language, did express agreement on the statement that “natural language has no logic.” But logicians and philosophers of language, even those who regarded natural languages as “illogical” in various ways, made crucial advances in semantic analysis that paved the way for contemporary formal semantics. Chomsky, from a very different angle, considered the invented languages of logic to be so different from any natural language that he doubted that logicians’ work on the formal syntax and semantics of logical languages could possibly be of any interest or usefulness for linguistics, and he therefore rejected Bar-Hillel’s exhortation in the early 1950’s for greater cooperation between logicians and linguists in syntax and semantics. It was the logician and philosopher Richard Montague, a student of Tarski’s, who had the greatest direct impact on the development of contemporary formal semantics, with his theory of “universal grammar” that encompassed both formal and natural languages, constructed in part on the basis of his own typed intensional logic. From his seminal works in the late 1960’s and early 1970’s, as well as work by David Lewis, Terry Parsons, Richmond Thomason, Max Cresswell, and linguists Partee, Lauri Karttunen, Ed Keenan, David Dowty, Emmon Bach and others, interdisciplinary collaboration led to a rapid expansion of the field. In this talk I’ll review some of this background and reflect on key ideas and controversies in the development of formal semantics. I’ll talk about some of the pivotal contributions by logicians as formal semantics and pragmatics developed after Montague’s untimely death in 1971, and I’ll also discuss the “naturalizing” influence that linguists have had on the field as it has become more and more a branch of linguistics. At the end I’ll discuss the apparent incompatibility of Chomsky’s view of linguistics as a branch of psychology and the anti-psychologistic Fregean tradition viewing meanings as abstract objects, a foundational tension that has not hindered progress but is still not fully resolved |
Thursday, December 3, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science |
|||||
Discussion. On de Finetti's representation theorem for exchangeability, Chapter 7, "Unification," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Thursday, November 12, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Computer Science, Mathematics, Philosophy |
|||||
Discussion. Chapter 8, "Algorithmic Randomness," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Thursday, November 5, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Department of Computer Science |
|||||
Discussion. Chapter 6, "Inverse Inference: From Bayes and Laplace to Modern Statistics," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Thursday, October 29, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Cailin O'Connor |
Department of Logic & Philosophy of Science |
||||
Abstract. Standard accounts of convention include notions of arbitrariness. But many have conceived of conventionality as an all or nothing affair. In this paper, I develop a framework for thinking of conventions as coming in degrees of arbitrariness. In doing so, I introduce an information theoretic measure intended to capture the degree to which a solution to a certain social problem could have been otherwise. As the paper argues, this framework can help improve explanation aimed at the cultural evolution of social traits. Good evolutionary explanations recognize that most functional traits are also conventional, at least to some degree, and vice versa. |
Thursday, October 22, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Paul Krasucki |
Security |
||||
Discussion. Chapter 5, "Mathematics," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Thursday, October 15, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Jayant Shah |
Department of Mathematics |
||||
Discussion. Chapter 4, "Frequency," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Thursday, October 8, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Ada Coronado |
Department of Philosophy |
||||
Discussion. Chapter 3, "Psychology," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Wednesday September 30, 11:00 AM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Todd Stambaugh |
Department of Mathematics and Computer Science |
||||
Coincidence of Bargaining Solution ‖Slides Abstract. In 1950, a month before his dissertation on non-coorperative games was accepted at Princeton and 3 months after his famous solution concept was announced to the world in the Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, John Nash had published "The Bargaining Problem," in which he proposed the titular problem and gave the first solution. In the years after, several other solutions were developed, notably those by Kalai and Smorodinsky, Kalai, and Harsanyi. In this talk I will outline the problem itself, present four different solutions, and describe the precise conditions under which various sets of these solutions coincide. |
Thursday, September 17, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
Larry Moss |
Department of Mathematics |
||||
Discussion. Chapter 2, "Judgment," from Persi Diaconis and Brian Skyrms' Ten Great Ideas about Chance |
Thursday, August 20, 6:30 PM EST | |||||
Join by Zoom (click one) | Desktop Client Web Client | ||||
José Luis Bermúdez |
Department of Philosophy |
||||
Rational Frames? |